Skip to content

Latest commit

 

History

History
1777 lines (1401 loc) · 40.3 KB

THEOREMS.md

File metadata and controls

1777 lines (1401 loc) · 40.3 KB

Theorem Proving

Theorem proving is the main difference between Kind and traditional pure functional languages like Haskell. Since proving theorems require certain techniques that aren't common in these languages, this tutorial aims to fill that gap, supplementing a reader that is familiar with basic functional programming concepts (like recursion, pattern matching and algebraic datatypes) with the required knowledge to start proving theorems right now.

Before starting, make sure to install Kind via Haskell or JavaScript (example: npm i -g kind-lang), clone this repository (https://github.com/Kindelia/Kind) and cd into the kind/base directory (you must be there for now). You'll be editing the Main.kind file only. Open it in your favorite editor and type kind Main.kind to type-check it.

The Equal type

To start proving theorems, first you must be aware of the Equal type:

type Equal <A: Type> (a: A) ~ (b: A) {
  refl ~ (b = a)
}

If that looks alien to you, don't worry for now, it will become clear. The Equal type has only one constructor, refl, which has the following type:

Equal.refl : (A: Type) -> (x: A) -> Equal(A,x,x)

That means refl receives a type (A), and element x of type A, and returns Equal(A,x,x). As an example, the program below:

two_is_two: Equal(Nat, 2, 2)
  Equal.refl(Nat, 2)

Is a proof that 2 == 2. Not that scary, right? Since Equal and refl are common, there is a shortcut to write them. The program above is equivalent to:

two_is_two: 2 == 2
  refl

Make sure to replace the contents of Main.kind by the snipped above, and type kind Main.kind to test it. You should see:

two_is_two: 2 == 2

All terms check.

Meaning that we indeed proved that 2 and 2 are equal. We can use Equal.refl to prove an equality when both sides are equal, or when they reduce to the same term. That means this also works:

two_is_two: (1 + 1) == 2 
  refl

Because (1 + 1) is a concrete value that computes to 2. Now, of course, proving that two concrete values are equal isn't that interesting. The real fun starts when you start mixing letters; aka, variables; in these equations. Theorem proving, in its most essential form, is all about techniques to manipulate these equations until you get both sides to be identical. That's what we're going to do through all this tutorial. Ready? Let's go!


Our first theorem: double negation

We'll start proving a simple theorem: that, for any Boolean b, not(not(b)) == b. In other words, we'll prove that negating a boolean twice results on the original boolean. To start this proof, we give the theorem a name, a type, and a body (a goal):

double_negation(b: Bool): Bool.not(Bool.not(b)) == b
  ?a

We now run kind Main.kind. That will display:

Goal ?a:
With type: Bool.not(Bool.not(b)) == b
With context:
- b: Bool

That just tells us that we must fill the body of double_negation with a proof that not(not(b)) == b; nothing new here. Let's try using Equal.refl:

double_negation(b: Bool): Bool.not(Bool.not(b)) == b
  Equal.refl(Bool, b)

This will show a type error:

Type mismatch.
- Expected: Bool.not(Bool.not(b)) == b
- Detected: b == b
With context:
- b: Bool

That's because Equal.refl(Bool, b) proves that b == b, but we want a proof that Bool.not(Bool.not(b)) == b. Yes, we, humans, know that Bool.not(Bool.not(b)) should always reduce to b, but the machine, Kind, doesn't know that. Why? Let's see the definition of Bool.not (from Bool.kind):

Bool.not(b: Bool): Bool
  case b {
    true: false
    false: true
  }

When Kind sees Bool.not(Bool.not(b)), it reduces it to:

Bool.not(case b { true: false, false: true })

But now the inner case is stuck, trying to pattern-match on b. It can't choose any branch, because it doesn't know what b is. It isn't true, it isn't false. It is just a variable. That is the only reason Kind is not able to tell that Bool.not(Bool.not(b)) and b are the same. But we can help it with a case analysis. That is, we can pattern-match on b:

double_negation(b: Bool): not(not(b)) == b
  case b {
    true: ?a
    false: ?b
  }

Check it with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?a:
With type: Bool.not(Bool.not(b)) == b
With context:
- b: Bool

Goal ?b:
With type: Bool.not(Bool.not(b)) == b
With context:
- b: Bool

Now, instead of one goal, we have two goals. But Kind is still demanding a proof that Bool.not(Bool.not(b)) == b in both, so, that wasn't very helpful. But consider the following: on the true case, we know that b is true, because we just pattern-matched it. Similarly, on the false case, we know that b is false. Wouldn't it be great if Kind noticed that, and relaxed its demands by specializing b to its concrete value on each branch? We can ask Kind to do just that by adding a ! after the case expression:

double_negation(b: Bool): Bool.not(Bool.not(b)) == b
  case b {
    true: ?a
    false: ?b
  }!

Here, ! stands for "please, be less demanding and specialize b to its concrete values on each case". By running kind Main.kind, we now see:

Goal ?a:
With type: Bool.not(Bool.not(Bool.true)) == Bool.true
With context:
- b: Bool

Goal ?b:
With type: Bool.not(Bool.not(Bool.false)) == Bool.false
With context:
- b: Bool

Kind now demands a proof that not(not(true)) == true on the first case, and a proof that not(not(false)) == false on the second one. That's great, because the variable b is gone and the case b inside not is now "unstuck" and ready to compute. To see that this is true, Kind allows us to inspect and reduce a goal by writing - after it:

double_negation(b: Bool): Bool.not(Bool.not(b)) == b
  case b {
    true: ?a-
    false: ?b-
  }!

Running kind Main.kind, we see:

Goal ?a:
With type: Bool.not-10(Bool.not-22(Bool.true-30)) == Bool.true-3
With context:
- b: Bool

Goal ?b:
With type: Bool.not-10(Bool.not-22(Bool.false-30)) == Bool.false-3
With context:
- b: Bool

Notice how a -N was added after each reducible expression. That's a label. We can ask Kind to reduce any of these by writting that label after the goal. Let's reduce the inner not (the one labelled -22) on each branch:

double_negation(b: Bool): Bool.not(Bool.not(b)) == b
  case b {
    true: ?a-22
    false: ?b-22
  }!

Running kind Main.kind, we see:

Goal ?a:
With type: Bool.not(Bool.false) == Bool.true
With context:
- b: Bool

Goal ?b:
With type: Bool.not(Bool.true) == Bool.false
With context:
- b: Bool

Notice how the inner Bool.not was reduced, going from, on the ?a branch, not(not(true)) == true to not(false) == true. We can repeat the step above to reduce the last not:

double_negation(b: Bool): Bool.not(Bool.not(b)) == b
  case b {
    true: ?a-22-10
    false: ?b-22-10
  }!

Running kind Main.kind:

Goal ?a:
With type: Bool.true == Bool.true
With context:
- b: Bool

Goal ?b:
With type: Bool.false == Bool.false
With context:
- b: Bool

That means Kind wants us to prove that true == true and false == false on each branch respectively. That is easy: since both sides are equal, we can just use refl:

double_negation(b: Bool): Bool.not(Bool.not(b)) == b
  case b {
    true: refl
    false: refl
  }!

By running kind Main.kind, we see:

double_negation: (b:Bool) Bool.not(Bool.not(b)) == b

All terms check.

That means our first proof is complete, and not(not(b)) == b is indeed true. Good job!

Note that you could have written refl on its full form (for example, Equal.refl(Bool, Bool.true)) instead of just refl. Note also that this last step of reducing the goal with - is optional. If you knew that not(not(true)) == true would reduce to true == true, you could have just written refl directly. Learning to use - can be very handy when you have goals too complex to reduce in your head, so keep it in your toolbelt!

An easy theorem: and(true, b) == b

Let's now prove that and(true, b) == b. That's true because, if b is true, then the equation becomes and(true,true) == true, which reduces to true == true, which holds. And, if b is false, the equation becomes and(true,false) == false, which reduces to false == false, which holds. Let's prove it. As always, we start by writting a name, a type and a body:

and_true_b(b: Bool): Bool.and(true, b) == b
  ?a

By running kind main.kind, we see:

Goal ?a:
With type: Bool.and(Bool.true,b) == b
With context:
- b: Bool

Notice that there is a variable b on the left side of the equation. That means that we must pattern-match, because it is stuck... or is it? Let's recall the definition of Bool.and (from Bool.kind):

Bool.and(a: Bool, b: Bool): Bool
  case a {
    true: b,
    false: false,
  }

Notice that this function only pattern-matches on a, not on b. That means Bool.and(true,b) is not stuck, and immediately reduces to b. We can convince ourselves of that by reducing Bool.and. First, add a - to the goal:

and_true_b(b: Bool): Bool.and(true, b) == b
  ?a-

Run it with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?a:
With type: Bool.and-18(Bool.true-26,b) == b
With context:
- b: Bool

Apply the Bool.and labelled with 18:

and_true_b(b: Bool): Bool.and(true, b) == b
  ?a-18

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?a:
With type: b == b
With context:
- b: Bool

Since both sides are equal, we can complete this proof with refl:

and_true_b(b: Bool): Bool.and(true, b) == b
  refl

Check with kind Main.kind:

and_true_b: (b:Bool) Bool.and(Bool.true,b) == b

All terms check.

And done! Notice how we didn't need to use case on this proof. The lesson is: having variables inside an expression doesn't mean it is stuck, it depends on the definition of the used functions. As a rule of thumb, when proving a theorem, don't just pattern-match every variable you see on the goal. Always use - to test if your goal can be simplified as is. Only if it can't you should pattern-match to specialize a variable to its concrete values.

A hard theorem: and(b, true) == b

Let's now prove and(b, true) == b:

and_b_true(b: Bool): Bool.and(b, true) == b
  ?a

That is almost identical to the last theorem we proved (and(true, b) == b), so it should be just refl too, right? Wrong! Let's see what happens if we try to reduce Bool.and. To do so, first, write - after the goal:

and_b_true(b: Bool): Bool.and(b, true) == b
  ?a-

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?a:
With type: Bool.and-18(b,Bool.true-14) == b
With context:
- b: Bool

Reduce the Bool.and labelled with 18:

and_b_true(b: Bool): Bool.and(b, true) == b
  ?a-18

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?a:
With type: b((a) Bool,Bool.true,Bool.false) == b
With context:
- b: Bool

What? Unlike the previous theorem, reducing Bool.and didn't turn our type into b == b immediately. Instead, it became b(...) == b. That's because Bool.and is defined to pattern-match on the first argument, which, now, is the variable b, instead of the concrete boolean true. That causes the left side to be stuck trying to apply b to these things. To get it unstuck, we must use a case on b:

and_b_true(b: Bool): Bool.and(b, true) == b
  case b {
    true: ?a
    false: ?b
  }!

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?a:
With type: Bool.and(Bool.true,Bool.true) == Bool.true
With context:
- b: Bool

Goal ?b:
With type: Bool.and(Bool.false,Bool.true) == Bool.false
With context:
- b: Bool

Now we could have used - to reduce Bool.and on both goals to convince ourselves that they reduce to true == true and false == false respectively. Since I already know that, I'll just write refl on both cases:

and_b_true(b: Bool): Bool.and(b, true) == b
  case b {
    true: refl
    false: refl
  }!

That completes our third proof. The lesson is: again, use - to see how your goal reduces, use case to specialize stuck variables, and use refl when you manage to get two sides equal. With this simple procedure and enough patience, you can prove any equality theorem.

A hard theorem made easy: b == and(b,true)

Let's now prove that b == and(b,true):

right_and_b_true(b: Bool): b == Bool.and(b, true)
  ?a

Since we have a variable b, and not a concrete value, as the first argument of and(b,true), and, since and pattern-matches on its first argument, then we must need a pattern-match on this proof. Right? Kinda. Indeed we could do that:

right_and_b_true(b: Bool): b == Bool.and(b, true)
  case b {
    true: refl
    false: refl
  }!

And that would complete our proof. But in this case, since we have just proven and(b,true) == b, which is the same thing just flipped,that means we can reuse the former proof to prove right_and_b_true:

and_b_true(b: Bool): Bool.and(b, true) == b
  case b {
    true: refl
    false: refl
  }!

right_and_b_true(b: Bool): b == Bool.and(b, true)
  mirror(and_b_true(b))

Here, mirror : (A: Type) -> (a: A) -> (b: B) -> Equal(A,a,b) -> Equal(A,b,a) is a standard function that flips the two arguments of an equality. That is, it turns a == b into b == a. The lesson here is that not always we will prove equalities with refl directly. If we did that, every proof would be huge! Instead, we can use former proofs inside later proofs, simplifying their code. This is a functional programming language, after all. Modularism, function reuse and clean code apply to proofs too!

Exercises

As an exercise, prove the following theorems:

and_false_b(b: Bool): Bool.and(false, b) == false
  ?a

and_b_false(b: Bool): Bool.and(b, false) == false
  ?a

or_true_b(b: Bool): Bool.or(true, b) == true
  ?a

or_b_true(b: Bool): Bool.or(b, true) == true
  ?a

or_false_b(b: Bool): Bool.or(false, b) == b
  ?a

or_b_false(b: Bool): Bool.or(b, false) == b
  ?a

eql_b_b(b: Bool): Bool.eql(b, b) == true
  ?a

demorgan_0(a: Bool, b: Bool): Bool.not(Bool.and(a,b)) == Bool.or(Bool.not(a),Bool.not(b))
  ?a

demorgan_1(a: Bool, b: Bool): Bool.not(Bool.or(a,b)) == Bool.and(Bool.not(a),Bool.not(b))
  ?a

An inductive proof: half(double(n)) == n

Let's now prove the simplest "inductive" theorem on natural numbers: that the half of the double of a natural number is itself. As usual, we begin by writting a name, a type and a body:

half_double_theorem(n: Nat): Nat.half(Nat.double(n)) == n
  ?a

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?a:
With type: Nat.half(Nat.double(n)) == n
With context:
- n: Nat

Here, we could try using - to reduce Nat.double and check if it simplifies. Let's recall the definition of Nat.double and Nat.half:

Nat.double(n: Nat): Nat
  case n {
    zero: Nat.zero,
    succ: Nat.succ(Nat.succ(Nat.double(n.pred))),
  }

Nat.half(n: Nat): Nat
  case n {
    zero: Nat.zero,
    succ: case n.pred {
      zero: Nat.zero,
      succ: Nat.succ(Nat.half(n.pred.pred))
    }
  }

Since half uses case on n, it gets stuck, so we use case on n in our proof to unstuck it:

half_double_theorem(n: Nat): Nat.half(Nat.double(n)) == n
  case n {
    zero: ?a
    succ: ?b
  }!

Run with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?a:
With type: Nat.half(Nat.double(0)) == 0
With context:
- n: Nat

Goal ?b:
With type: Nat.half(Nat.double(Nat.succ(n.pred))) == Nat.succ(n.pred)
With context:
- n: Nat
- n.pred: Nat

On the zero case, we must prove that half(double(0)) == 0. This reduces to 0 == 0 (you can use - to verify that), so we just write refl:

half_double_theorem(n: Nat): Nat.half(Nat.double(n)) == n
  case n {
    zero: refl
    succ: ?b
  }!

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?b:
With type: Nat.half(Nat.double(Nat.succ(n.pred))) == Nat.succ(n.pred)
With context:
- n: Nat
- n.pred: Nat

Since there is just one goal left, that means the first case is correct. Now, for the succ case, remember that the successor of a number can be written as 1 + pred, where pred is the predecessor of n. As such, Kind demands us to prove that half(double(succ(pred))) == succ(pred). Let's try to simplify the left side of that equation. Write a - after the goal:

half_double_theorem(n: Nat): Nat.half(Nat.double(n)) == n
  case n {
    zero: refl
    succ: ?b-
  }!

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?b:
With type: Nat.half-10(Nat.double-22(Nat.succ-46(n.pred))) == Nat.succ-5(n.pred)
With context:
- n: Nat
- n.pred: Nat

Reduce the call to Nat.double (label 22):

half_double_theorem(n: Nat): Nat.half(Nat.double(n)) == n
  case n {
    zero: refl
    succ: ?b-22-
  }!

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?b:
With type: Nat.half-10(Nat.succ-22(Nat.succ-46(Nat.double-94(n.pred)))) == Nat.succ-5(n.pred)
With context:
- n: Nat
- n.pred: Nat

Reduce the call to Nat.half (label 10):

half_double_theorem(n: Nat): Nat.half(Nat.double(n)) == n
  case n {
    zero: refl
    succ: ?b-22-10
  }!

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?b:
With type: Nat.succ(Nat.half(Nat.double(n.pred))) == Nat.succ(n.pred)
With context:
- n: Nat
- n.pred: Nat

It seems like not much has changed, but we managed to get the Nat.succ out of the half(double(...)) expression. But now double is stuck on a variable again: n.pred. Remember . is just part of the name, n.pred is the predecessor of n. We could pattern-match on n.pred to unstuck it:

half_double_theorem(n: Nat): Nat.half(Nat.double(n)) == n
  case n {
    zero: refl
    succ: case n.pred {
      zero: ?a
      succ: ?b
    }!
  }!

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?a:
With type: Nat.half(Nat.double(1)) == 1
With context:
- n: Nat
- n.pred: Nat

Goal ?b:
With type: Nat.half(Nat.double(Nat.succ(Nat.succ(n.pred.pred)))) == Nat.succ(Nat.succ(n.pred.pred))
With context:
- n: Nat
- n.pred: Nat
- n.pred.pred: Nat

The first goal now demands a proof that half(double(1)) == 1. Both sides are now concrete and variable-free, so it reduces to 1 == 1, which can be completed with refl:

half_double_theorem(n: Nat): Nat.half(Nat.double(n)) == n
  case n {
    zero: refl
    succ: case n.pred {
      zero: refl
      succ: ?b
    }!
  }!

Great, we now proved the theorem for n = 0 and n = 1! But now the second goal now became:

Goal ?b:
With type: Nat.half(Nat.double(Nat.succ(Nat.succ(n.pred.pred)))) == Nat.succ(Nat.succ(n.pred.pred))
With context:
- n: Nat
- n.pred: Nat
- n.pred.pred: Nat

This is similar to the situation we had before. With enough patience, we could "lift" the Nat.succ out of the half(double(...)) expression:

Goal ?b:
With type: Nat.succ(Nat.succ(Nat.half(Nat.double(n.pred.pred)))) == Nat.succ(Nat.succ(n.pred.pred))
With context:
- n: Nat
- n.pred: Nat
- n.pred.pred: Nat

But now Nat.double is succ on n.pred.pred. We can use case on it too:

half_double_theorem(n: Nat): Nat.half(Nat.double(n)) == n
  case n {
    zero: refl
    succ: case n.pred {
      zero: refl
      succ: case n.pred.pred {
        zero: ?a
        succ: ?b
      }!
    }!
  }!

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?a:
With type: Nat.half(Nat.double(2)) == 2
With context:
- n: Nat
- n.pred: Nat
- n.pred.pred: Nat

Goal ?b:
With type: Nat.half(Nat.double(Nat.succ(Nat.succ(Nat.succ(n.pred.pred.pred))))) == Nat.succ(Nat.succ(Nat.succ(n.pred.pred.pred)))
With context:
- n: Nat
- n.pred: Nat
- n.pred.pred: Nat
- n.pred.pred.pred: Nat

Once again, the first goal is now concrete and we can fill with refl:

half_double_theorem(n: Nat): Nat.half(Nat.double(n)) == n
  case n {
    zero: refl
    succ: case n.pred {
      zero: refl
      succ: case n.pred.pred {
        zero: refl
        succ: ?b
      }!
    }!
  }!

That means we have proven our theorem for n=0, n=1 and n=2. But the last case is even larger. We could go on forever and forever, but we would never finish this proof because there are infinitely many natural numbers. So, we must take a step back where the loop began. Remember we had the following proof:

half_double_theorem(n: Nat): Nat.half(Nat.double(n)) == n
  case n {
    zero: refl
    succ: ?b-22-10
  }!

And the following goal (check with kind Main.kind):

Goal ?b:
With type: Nat.succ(Nat.half(Nat.double(n.pred))) == Nat.succ(n.pred)
With context:
- n: Nat
- n.pred: Nat

Since we were stuck on n.pred, we used case on it. But this resulted in an endless chain of cases. Let's instead try something different: instead of pattern-matching on n.pred, let's use half_double_theorem recursively on it:

half_double_theorem(n: Nat): Nat.half(Nat.double(n)) == n
  case n {
    zero: refl
    succ:
      let ind = half_double_theorem(n.pred)
      ?b-22-10
  }!

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?b:
With type: Nat.succ(Nat.half(Nat.double(n.pred))) == Nat.succ(n.pred)
With context:
- n: Nat
- n.pred: Nat
- ind: Nat.half(Nat.double(n.pred)) == n.pred

Our goal didn't change, but now we have a new variable, ind in our context. We gained it "for free" by calling half_double_theorem recursively on its predecessor. Since half_double_theorem returns half(double(n)) == n for any n, and since we applied it to n.pred, then ind has type half(double(n.pred)) == n.pred. That's the inductive hypothesis. Take a moment to realize that this type is almost the same as our goal: the only difference is that the goal has an extra Nat.succ on each side. We can apply a function to both sides of an equality using apply(f,e).

half_double_theorem(n: Nat): Nat.half(Nat.double(n)) == n
  case n {
    zero: refl
    succ:
      let ind = half_double_theorem(n.pred)
      let app = apply(Nat.succ, ind)
      ?b-22-10
  }!

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?b:
With type: Nat.succ(Nat.half(Nat.double(n.pred))) == Nat.succ(n.pred)
With context:
- n: Nat
- n.pred: Nat
- ind: Nat.half(Nat.double(n.pred)) == n.pred
- app: Nat.succ(Nat.half(Nat.double(n.pred))) == Nat.succ(n.pred)

The type of app is exactly the type of our goal, so we can complete the proof with it:

half_double_theorem(n: Nat): Nat.half(Nat.double(n)) == n
  case n {
    zero: refl
    succ:
      let ind = half_double_theorem(n.pred)
      let app = apply(Nat.succ, ind)
      app
  }!

Check with kind Main.kind:

half_double_theorem: (n:Nat) Nat.half(Nat.double(n)) == n

All terms check.

Great! This one was really hard, wasn't it? That's because the concept of induction is hard to grasp, yet, induction is nothing but a fancy name for recursion when used inside a proof. The lesson here is that there is a new way to "unstuck" a variable in a goal. Instead of pattern-matching on it (with case), we can apply the function recursively to it. This will give us "for free" a term of type a == b that is closer to the goal. Then, by manipulating that equation (with mirror and apply, for example), we can prove our goal.

A non-inductive proof: (0 + n) == n

Let's now prove that 0 + n == n for any n. We start as usual:

add_0_n(n: Nat): (0 + n) == n
  ?a

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?a:
With type: Nat.add(0,n) == n
With context:
- n: Nat

Kind asks us to prove Nat.add(0,n) == n. It would be tempting to pattern-match on n. But let's recall the definition of Nat.add (from Nat.kind):

Nat.add(n: Nat, m: Nat): Nat
  case n {
    zero: m,
    succ: Nat.succ(Nat.add(n.pred, m)),
  }

Since it pattern-matches on the first argument, and since the first argument of 0 + n is concrete, then the goal reduces immediately to n == n. You can verify that by using the - feature. As such, this proof is trivial:

add_0_n(n: Nat): (0 + n) == n
  refl

Check with kind Main.kind:

add_0_n: (n:Nat) Nat.add(0,n) == n

All terms check.

Done!

An inductive proof: (n + 0) == n

Let's now prove (n + 0) == n:

add_n_0(n: Nat): (n + 0) == n
  ?a

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?a:
With type: Nat.add(n,0) == n
With context:
- n: Nat

In this case, the first argument of Nat.add is a variable, n, instead of a concrete value like 0. It will get stuck. As usual, we unstuck it by using case:

add_n_0(n: Nat): (n + 0) == n
  case n {
    zero: ?a
    succ: ?b
  }!

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?a:
With type: Nat.add(0,0) == 0
With context:
- n: Nat

Goal ?b:
With type: Nat.add(Nat.succ(n.pred),0) == Nat.succ(n.pred)
With context:
- n: Nat
- n.pred: Nat

We can reduce Nat.add on the goal ?a using -:

add_n_0(n: Nat): (n + 0) == n
  case n {
    zero: ?a-18
    succ: ?b
  }!

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?a:
With type: 0 == 0
With context:
- n: Nat

Goal ?b:
With type: Nat.add(Nat.succ(n.pred),0) == Nat.succ(n.pred)
With context:
- n: Nat
- n.pred: Nat

Since both sides of the ?a goal are equal, we complete it with refl:

add_n_0(n: Nat): (n + 0) == n
  case n {
    zero: refl
    succ: ?b
  }!

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?b:
With type: Nat.add(Nat.succ(n.pred),0) == Nat.succ(n.pred)
With context:
- n: Nat
- n.pred: Nat

On the left side of the goal ?b, we have add(succ(n.pred),0). From the definition of Nat.add, we know that this is equivalent to succ(add(n.pred,0)), so we use - to reduce add and simplify the goal:

add_n_0(n: Nat): (n + 0) == n
  case n {
    zero: refl
    succ: ?b-18
  }!

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?b:
With type: Nat.succ(Nat.add(n.pred,0)) == Nat.succ(n.pred)
With context:
- n: Nat
- n.pred: Nat

Now add has a variable, n.pred, on its first argument, so it is stuck. Instead of using case on n.pred - which will lead to an infinite cascade of cases - we use the inductive hypothesis. That is, we apply add_n_0 recursively to n.pred:

add_n_0(n: Nat): (n + 0) == n
  case n {
    zero: refl
    succ:
      let ind = add_n_0(n.pred)
      ?b-18
  }!

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?b:
With type: Nat.succ(Nat.add(n.pred,0)) == Nat.succ(n.pred)
With context:
- n: Nat
- n.pred: Nat
- ind: Nat.add(n.pred,0) == n.pred

Thanks to the inductive hypothesis, we gained ind: add(n.pred,0) == n.pred for free. The type of ind is almost equal to our goal, except that it is missing a Nat.succ on both sides. We add it using apply:

add_n_0(n: Nat): (n + 0) == n
  case n {
    zero: refl
    succ:
      let ind = add_n_0(n.pred)
      let app = apply(Nat.succ, ind)
      ?b-18
  }!

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?b:
With type: Nat.succ(Nat.add(n.pred,0)) == Nat.succ(n.pred)
With context:
- n: Nat
- n.pred: Nat
- ind: Nat.add(n.pred,0) == n.pred
- app: Nat.succ(Nat.add(n.pred,0)) == Nat.succ(n.pred)

The type of app is now the same as our goal, so we complete the proof with it:

add_n_0(n: Nat): (n + 0) == n
  case n {
    zero: refl
    succ:
      let ind = add_n_0(n.pred)
      let app = apply(Nat.succ, ind)
      app
  }!

Check with kind Main.kind:

add_n_0: (n:Nat) Nat.add(n,0) == n

All terms check.

Done! As you can see, proofs about natural numbers often follow this same structure. On the zero case, write refl. On the succ case, use the inductive hypothesis on n.pred and manipulate ind to reach the goal. Of course, it varies depending on what you're trying to prove, but often that's the way.

Exercises

As an exercise, prove the following theorems:

lte_0_n(n: Nat): Nat.lte(0, n) == true
  ?a

gte_n_0(n: Nat): Nat.gte(n, 0) == true
  ?b

eql_n_n(n: Nat): Nat.eql(n, n) == true
  ?c

is_even_double_n(n: Nat): Nat.is_even(Nat.double(n)) == true
  ?d

gte_succ_n_0(n: Nat): Nat.gte(Nat.succ(n), 0) == true
  ?e

gte_succ_n_n(n: Nat): Nat.gte(Nat.succ(n), n) == true
  ?f

Here, Nat.lte(a,b) stands for a <= b and Nat.gte(a,b) stands for a >= b for natural numbers a, b. Check their definitions on Nat.kind.

Proving an inequality: 1 != 0

In Kind, to prove that a theorem is true, we construct an element of the corresponding type. But how do we prove that something is not true? To do it, we must show that constructing an element of that type is impossible. The easiest way to do it is by contradiction: we first assume that the theorem holds and, based on that assumption, construct an element of the Empty type. Since the Empty type can't be constructed, then our theorem can't be true. But what is the Empty type?

Remember the Boolean type has 2 elements:

type Bool {
  true
  false
}

Similarly, the Unit type has 1 element:

type Unit {
  unit
}

And a Suit type has 4 elements:

type Suit {
  hearts
  spades
  clubs
  diamonds
}

If we can create a type with 1, 2 and 4 elements, can we create a type with 0 elements? Sure, that's the Empty type:

type Empty {
}

But what is the point of a type with zero elements? It is useless, right? Wrong! In fact it is one of the most useful types, because of how case expressions work, and the princible of explosion. In order for a case expression to be considered well-typed in Kind, you must provide a proof that it holds on each case. For example, recall the double negation theorem:

double_negation(b: Bool): Bool.not(Bool.not(b)) == b
  case b {
    true: refl
    false: refl
  }!

Here, Kind demanded us a proof of not(not(true)) == true on the true case, and a proof of not(not(false)) == false on the false case. Since we provided a proof for each case of b, the case expression returned a proof of not(not(b)) == b. That is, from a proof of each specific case (true / false) we generated a proof of the general case (a variable b : Bool). But what happens if we use case on a variable e of type Empty?

xablau(e: Empty): 1 == 0
  case e {
  }!

Here, Kind will demand us to prove that 1 == 0 holds for each possible value of e. But e has no case, so, technically, we satisfied Kind's demand by doing nothing. Kind then returns a proof that 1 == 0 holds for every possible value of e. So, did we just prove that 1 == 0? No! Because xablau is a function that demands an element of the type Empty. But the Empty type has no elements, so we can never call xablau!

That's the principle of explosion: from an absurd, we can derive any other absurd. That's why Empty is so useful. If we can derive Empty from a theorem, then that theorem is definitely false. For example, let's prove that 1 == 0 is not true. We write a function:

one_neq_zero(e: 1 == 0): Empty
  ?a

Which stands for "if 1 == 0, then we can construct an element of the Empty type". Which can be read as "1 == 0 is a false theorem".

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?a:
With type: Empty
With context:
- e: 1 == 0

That means that, to prove that "1 == 0" is indeed false, our goal is to construct an element of the Empty type, based on the assumption that 1 == 0 (named e).

To do it, you must understand two other things. First, that we can have expressions on types. For example:

two: if true then Nat else String
  2

This is a perfectly valid Kind definition. Notice how we used an expression (if) inside the type of two. This is completely allowed. If you replaced if true by if false, the program above wouldn't type-check anymore (try it!). We can also write inline type annotations in Kind with ::, so, for example:

let two = 2 :: if true then Nat else String

Is also valid.

Second, we can rewrite a by b inside a type if we have a proof that a == b. For example, suppose we had the following context:

eq: n == 2
xs: Vector(Nat, n)

That is, we have a vector xs of n natural numbers, and a proof eq that n == 2. We can use rewrite and eq to cast xs to type Vector(Nat, 2):

let ys = xs :: rewrite x in Vector(Nat, x) with eq

This would give us the following context:

eq: n == 2
xs: Vector(Nat, n)
ys: Vector(Nat, 2)

Take a moment to make sure the above makes sense to you. If you want to, you may check the definition of rewrite on the Equal.kind file (although that may be a little bit too indimidating for now!).

With these two insights in mind (that we have expressions inside types, and that we can rewrite equal values inside types), we can prove that one_neq_zero by using a very clever trick. Ready? Here it is:

one_neq_zero(e: 1 == 0): Empty
  let a = 42 :: if Nat.eql(1,1) then Nat else Empty
  let b = a  :: rewrite x in (if Nat.eql(1,x) then Nat else Empty) with e
  b

Now take a breath, and let me explain what is going on.

First, we created a local variable, a, of type if Nat.eql(1,1) then Nat else Empty. Since Nat.eql(1,1) is true, then a must have type Nat. So, we just write 42, but any number would work.

Second, we used the fact that 1 == 0 to replace the second 1 on the type of 42, from 1 to 0. That means that b will have type if Nat.eql(1,0) then Nat else Empty. But Nat.eql(1,0) is false, so, b has type Empty. Which is what we were trying to construct!

In other words, we managed to create an element of type Empty by assuming that 1 == 0, plus a clever use of rewrite to "trick" Kind. Since the Empty type has no elements, that means that, by contradiction, 1 is different of 0. In other words, whenever we have a proof in the following shape:

a_neq_b(e: a == b): Empty
  proof_by_contradiction

Then we know, for sure, that a and b are different. Since this is so common, you can also write it as a != b:

a_neq_b: a != b
  (e) proof_by_contradiction

Here, a != b is a synonym of Not(a == b), which is a synonym of (e: a == b) -> Empty, which is why we write a lambda (e) on the body of a_neq_b.

Uff! That was a lot of information. Let's prove another inequality, but this time being a little bit more straightforward.

Proving another inequality: 3 != 2

Let's now prove that 3 != 2. As usual, start with the name, type and body:

three_neq_two: 3 != 2
  ?a

Check it with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?a:
With type: Not(3 == 2)

As expected, Kind just tells us we must prove Not(3 == 2), which is the same as (e: 3 == 2) -> Empty. Since that is a function, we create a lambda:

three_neq_two: 3 != 2
  (e) ?a

Check it with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?a:
With type: Empty
With context:
- e: 3 == 2

Now Kind is demanding that we derive an element of type Empty given a value of type 3 == 2. We could proceed by using the rewrite trick above, but, let's be honest, it is confusing and doing it every time would be annoying. Instead, we will use the following function, exported by Bool.kind:

Bool.true_neq_false: true != false

Which, remember, is equivalent to:

Bool.true_neq_false: (e: true == false) -> Empty

So, here is the plan: since we have e : 3 == 2, and a function that, given true == false returns Empty (which is our goal), then we'll just manipulate e to transform its type from 3 == 2 to true == false, and then we'll send it to Bool.true_neq_false, resulting in Empty (our goal). Let's use Nat.pred to subtract 1 from both sides:

three_neq_two: 3 != 2
  (e)
  let e0 = apply(Nat.pred, e)
  ?a

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?a:
With type: Empty
With context:
- e: 3 == 2
- e0: 2 == 1

Now we have e0: 2 == 1. Let's do it again:

three_neq_two: 3 != 2
  (e)
  let e0 = apply(Nat.pred, e)
  let e1 = apply(Nat.pred, e0)
  ?a

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?a:
With type: Empty
With context:
- e: 3 == 2
- e0: 2 == 1
- e1: 1 == 0

Now we have e1 : 1 == 0. Let's now apply Nat.is_zero to both sides:

three_neq_two: 3 != 2
  (e)
  let e0 = apply(Nat.pred, e)
  let e1 = apply(Nat.pred, e0)
  let e2 = apply(Nat.is_zero, e1)
  ?a

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?a:
With type: Empty
With context:
- e: 3 == 2
- e0: 2 == 1
- e1: 1 == 0
- e2: false == true

Let's now flip e2 using mirror:

three_neq_two: 3 != 2
  (e)
  let e0 = apply(Nat.pred, e)
  let e1 = apply(Nat.pred, e0)
  let e2 = apply(Nat.is_zero, e1)
  let e3 = mirror(e2)
  ?a

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?a:
With type: Empty
With context:
- e: 3 == 2
- e0: 2 == 1
- e1: 1 == 0
- e2: false == true
- e3: true == false

Perfect, we now have e3: true == false in our context. Since Bool.true_neq_false receives true == false and returns Empty (our goal), we just apply it to e3:

three_neq_two: 3 != 2
  (e)
  let e0 = apply(Nat.pred, e)
  let e1 = apply(Nat.pred, e0)
  let e2 = apply(Nat.is_zero, e1)
  let e3 = mirror(e2)
  Bool.true_neq_false(e3)

Check with kind Main.kind:

three_neq_two: Not(3 == 2)

All terms check.

Perfect!

Proving an inequality with variables: not(b) != b

Let's now prove that not(b) != b. We start as usual:

not_a_neq_a(b: Bool): Bool.not(b) != b
  ?a

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?a:
With type: Not(Bool.not(b) == b)
With context:
- a: Bool

As expected, Kind demands that we prove Not(not(b) == b), which is the same as (not(b) == b) -> Empty. Since that is a function, we add a lambda:

not_a_neq_a(b: Bool): Bool.not(b) != b
  (e) ?a

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?a:
With type: Empty
With context:
- a: Bool
- e: Bool.not(b) == b

Now we must construct Empty from e: not(b) == b. Let's pattern-match on b:

not_a_neq_a(b: Bool): Bool.not(b) != b
  (e)
  case b {
    true: ?a
    false: ?b
  }!

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?a:
With type: Empty
With context:
- b: Bool
- e: Bool.not(b) == b

Goal ?b:
With type: Empty
With context:
- b: Bool
- e: Bool.not(b) == b

This isn't helpful: we now have two branches with identical goals and contexts. But notice that b is true on the first branch, and false on the second branch, yet e: Bool.not(b) == b wasn't "updated" to reflect that fact. Can we update it? Sure: just move the lambda to inside the case expression. This will allow Kind to rewrite the type of e with the concrete values of b on each branch:

not_a_neq_a(b: Bool): Bool.not(b) != b
  case b {
    true: (e) ?a
    false: (e) ?b
  }!

Check with kind Main.kind:

Goal ?a:
With type: Empty
With context:
- b: Bool
- e: Bool.not(Bool.true) == Bool.true

Goal ?b:
With type: Empty
With context:
- b: Bool
- e: Bool.not(Bool.false) == Bool.false

Great! now we have e: false == true in one branch, and e: true == false on the other, and we must prove Empty. Now, remember that we can use Bool.true_neq_false and Bool.false_neq_true to create Empty from true == false and false == true respectively. As such, we just apply these functions to e:

not_a_neq_a(b: Bool): Bool.not(b) != b
  case b {
    true: (e) Bool.false_neq_true(e)
    false: (e) Bool.true_neq_false(e)
  }!

Check with kind Main.kind:

not_a_neq_a: (b:Bool) Not(Bool.not(b) == b)

All terms check.

Perfect! Notice that here we did something new: we used case of to specialize the value of a variable on the context, not the goal, to reflect the concrete value of b on each branch. Another way to do it is by using the with notation:

not_a_neq_a(b: Bool): Bool.not(b) != b
  (e)
  case b
  with e : (Bool.not(b) == b) {
    true: Bool.false_neq_true(e)
    false: Bool.true_neq_false(e)
  }!

This "moves" e: Bool.not(b) == b to inside the pattern-match, specializing b on its type. It has the same effect of moving the lambda inside. It may be more or less verbose depending of what you're trying to prove.

Exercises

Prove the following inequalities:

or_true_a_neq_false(a: Bool): Bool.or(true, a) != false
  ?a

or_a_true_neq_false(a: Bool): Bool.or(a, true) != false
  ?a

and_false_a_neq_true(a: Bool): Bool.and(false, a) != true
  ?a

and_a_false_neq_true(a: Bool): Bool.and(a, false) != true
  ?a

Boss fight

These theorems are harder than the rest, but can be proven from the techniques presented here:


add_succ_n_m(n: Nat, m: Nat): Nat.add(Nat.succ(n), m) == Nat.succ(Nat.add(n, m))
  ?a

add_n_succ_m(n: Nat, m: Nat): Nat.add(n, Nat.succ(m)) == Nat.succ(Nat.add(n, m))
  ?a

add_a_b(a: Nat, b: Nat): (a + b) == (b + a)
  ?a

succ_n_neq_n(n: Nat): Nat.succ(n) != n
  ?a

Hints:

  • To prove add_a_b, use add_0_n and add_n_succ_m.

  • To prove succ_n_neq_n, use case to specialize e (like on not_a_neq_a) and the inductive hypothesis.

If you got here congratulations! For more challenges read our problem list for newcomers