This repository has been archived by the owner on Jul 23, 2021. It is now read-only.
-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 23
/
Tactics.v
1239 lines (982 loc) · 42 KB
/
Tactics.v
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
(** * Tactics: More Basic Tactics *)
(** This chapter introduces several more proof strategies and
tactics that allow us to prove more interesting properties of
functional programs. We will see:
- how to use auxiliary lemmas in both "forward-style" and
"backward-style" proofs;
- how to reason about data constructors (in particular, how to use
the fact that they are injective and disjoint);
- how to create a strong induction hypothesis (and when such
strengthening is required); and
- more details on how to reason by case analysis. *)
Require Export Poly.
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * The [apply] Tactic *)
(** We often encounter situations where the goal to be proved is
exactly the same as some hypothesis in the context or some
previously proved lemma. *)
Theorem silly1 : forall (n m o p : nat),
n = m ->
[n;o] = [n;p] ->
[n;o] = [m;p].
Proof.
intros n m o p eq1 eq2.
rewrite <- eq1.
(** At this point, we could finish with "[rewrite -> eq2.
reflexivity.]" as we have done several times before. We can
achieve the same effect in a single step by using the [apply]
tactic instead: *)
apply eq2. Qed.
(** The [apply] tactic also works with _conditional_ hypotheses
and lemmas: if the statement being applied is an implication, then
the premises of this implication will be added to the list of
subgoals needing to be proved. *)
Theorem silly2 : forall (n m o p : nat),
n = m ->
(forall (q r : nat), q = r -> [q;o] = [r;p]) ->
[n;o] = [m;p].
Proof.
intros n m o p eq1 eq2.
apply eq2. apply eq1. Qed.
(** You may find it instructive to experiment with this proof
and see if there is a way to complete it using just [rewrite]
instead of [apply]. *)
(** Typically, when we use [apply H], the statement [H] will
begin with a [forall] that binds some _universal variables_. When
Coq matches the current goal against the conclusion of [H], it
will try to find appropriate values for these variables. For
example, when we do [apply eq2] in the following proof, the
universal variable [q] in [eq2] gets instantiated with [n] and [r]
gets instantiated with [m]. *)
Theorem silly2a : forall (n m : nat),
(n,n) = (m,m) ->
(forall (q r : nat), (q,q) = (r,r) -> [q] = [r]) ->
[n] = [m].
Proof.
intros n m eq1 eq2.
apply eq2. apply eq1. Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, optional (silly_ex) *)
(** Complete the following proof without using [simpl]. *)
Theorem silly_ex :
(forall n, evenb n = true -> oddb (S n) = true) ->
evenb 3 = true ->
oddb 4 = true.
Proof.
intros H1 H2.
apply H1. apply H2.
Qed.
(** To use the [apply] tactic, the (conclusion of the) fact
being applied must match the goal exactly -- for example, [apply]
will not work if the left and right sides of the equality are
swapped. *)
Theorem silly3_firsttry : forall (n : nat),
true = beq_nat n 5 ->
beq_nat (S (S n)) 7 = true.
Proof.
intros n H.
simpl.
(* Here we cannot use [apply] directly *)
Abort.
(** In this case we can use the [symmetry] tactic, which switches the
left and right sides of an equality in the goal. *)
Theorem silly3 : forall (n : nat),
true = beq_nat n 5 ->
beq_nat (S (S n)) 7 = true.
Proof.
intros n H.
symmetry.
simpl. (* Actually, this [simpl] is unnecessary, since
[apply] will perform simplification first. *)
apply H. Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars (apply_exercise1) *)
(** (_Hint_: You can use [apply] with previously defined lemmas, not
just hypotheses in the context. Remember that [SearchAbout] is
your friend.) *)
Theorem rev_exercise1 : forall (l l' : list nat),
l = rev l' ->
l' = rev l.
Proof.
intros l l' H.
rewrite -> H.
symmetry.
apply rev_involutive.
Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 1 star, optional (apply_rewrite) *)
(** Briefly explain the difference between the tactics [apply] and
[rewrite]. What are the situations where both can usefully be
applied? *)
(* When we need to use global variables, "apply" is better than "rewrite". *)
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * The [apply ... with ...] Tactic *)
(** The following silly example uses two rewrites in a row to
get from [[a,b]] to [[e,f]]. *)
Example trans_eq_example : forall (a b c d e f : nat),
[a;b] = [c;d] ->
[c;d] = [e;f] ->
[a;b] = [e;f].
Proof.
intros a b c d e f eq1 eq2.
rewrite -> eq1. rewrite -> eq2. reflexivity. Qed.
(** Since this is a common pattern, we might like to pull it out
as a lemma recording, once and for all, the fact that equality is
transitive. *)
Theorem trans_eq : forall (X:Type) (n m o : X),
n = m -> m = o -> n = o.
Proof.
intros X n m o eq1 eq2. rewrite -> eq1. rewrite -> eq2.
reflexivity. Qed.
(** Now, we should be able to use [trans_eq] to prove the above
example. However, to do this we need a slight refinement of the
[apply] tactic. *)
Example trans_eq_example' : forall (a b c d e f : nat),
[a;b] = [c;d] ->
[c;d] = [e;f] ->
[a;b] = [e;f].
Proof.
intros a b c d e f eq1 eq2.
(** If we simply tell Coq [apply trans_eq] at this point, it can
tell (by matching the goal against the conclusion of the lemma)
that it should instantiate [X] with [[nat]], [n] with [[a,b]], and
[o] with [[e,f]]. However, the matching process doesn't determine
an instantiation for [m]: we have to supply one explicitly by
adding [with (m:=[c,d])] to the invocation of [apply]. *)
apply trans_eq with (m:=[c;d]). apply eq1. apply eq2. Qed.
(** Actually, we usually don't have to include the name [m] in
the [with] clause; Coq is often smart enough to figure out which
instantiation we're giving. We could instead write: [apply
trans_eq with [c;d]]. *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, optional (apply_with_exercise) *)
Example trans_eq_exercise : forall (n m o p : nat),
m = (minustwo o) ->
(n + p) = m ->
(n + p) = (minustwo o).
Proof.
intros n m o p H1 H2.
apply trans_eq with m. apply H2. apply H1.
Qed.
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * The [inversion] Tactic *)
(** Recall the definition of natural numbers:
Inductive nat : Type :=
| O : nat
| S : nat -> nat.
It is obvious from this definition that every number has one of
two forms: either it is the constructor [O] or it is built by
applying the constructor [S] to another number. But there is more
here than meets the eye: implicit in the definition (and in our
informal understanding of how datatype declarations work in other
programming languages) are two more facts:
- The constructor [S] is _injective_. That is, if [S n = S m], it
must be the case that [n = m].
- The constructors [O] and [S] are _disjoint_. That is, [O] is not
equal to [S n] for any [n]. *)
(** Similar principles apply to all inductively defined types: all
constructors are injective, and the values built from distinct
constructors are never equal. For lists, the [cons] constructor
is injective and [nil] is different from every non-empty list.
For booleans, [true] and [false] are different. (Since neither
[true] nor [false] take any arguments, their injectivity is not an
issue.) And so on. *)
(** Coq provides a tactic called [inversion] that allows us to
exploit these principles in proofs. To see how to use it, let's
show explicitly that the [S] constructor is injective: *)
Theorem S_injective : forall (n m : nat),
S n = S m ->
n = m.
Proof.
intros n m H.
(** By writing [inversion H] at this point, we ask Coq to
generate all equations that it can infer from [H] as additional
hypotheses, replacing variables in the goal as it goes. In the
present example, this amounts to adding a new hypothesis [H1 : n =
m] and replacing [n] by [m] in the goal. *)
inversion H. reflexivity. Qed.
(** Here's a more interesting example that shows how multiple
equations can be derived at once. *)
Theorem inversion_ex1 : forall (n m o : nat),
[n; m] = [o; o] ->
[n] = [m].
Proof.
intros n m o H. inversion H. reflexivity. Qed.
(** It is possible to name the equations that [inversion]
generates with an [as ...] clause: *)
Theorem inversion_ex2 : forall (n m : nat),
[n] = [m] ->
n = m.
Proof.
intros n o H. inversion H as [Hno]. reflexivity. Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 1 star (inversion_ex3) *)
Example inversion_ex3 : forall (X : Type) (x y z : X) (l j : list X),
x :: y :: l = z :: j ->
y :: l = x :: j ->
x = y.
Proof.
intros X x y z l j H0 H1.
inversion H1. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** While the injectivity of constructors allows us to reason
that [forall (n m : nat), S n = S m -> n = m], the converse of
this implication is an instance of a more general fact about
constructors and functions, which we will find useful below: *)
Theorem f_equal : forall (A B : Type) (f: A -> B) (x y: A),
x = y -> f x = f y.
Proof. intros A B f x y eq. rewrite eq. reflexivity. Qed.
(** When used on a hypothesis involving an equality between
_different_ constructors (e.g., [S n = O]), [inversion] solves the
goal immediately. To see why this makes sense, consider the
following proof: *)
Theorem beq_nat_0_l : forall n,
beq_nat 0 n = true -> n = 0.
Proof.
intros n.
(** We can proceed by case analysis on [n]. The first case is
trivial. *)
destruct n as [| n'].
- (* n = 0 *)
intros H. reflexivity.
(** However, the second one doesn't look so simple: assuming
[beq_nat 0 (S n') = true], we must show [S n' = 0], but the latter
clearly contradictory! The way forward lies in the assumption.
After simplifying the goal state, we see that [beq_nat 0 (S n') =
true] has become [false = true]: *)
- (* n = S n' *)
simpl.
(** If we use [inversion] on this hypothesis, Coq notices that
the subgoal we are working on is impossible, and therefore removes
it from further consideration. *)
intros H. inversion H. Qed.
(** This is an instance of a general logical principle known as
the _principle of explosion_, which asserts that a contradiction
entails anything, even false things. For instance: *)
Theorem inversion_ex4 : forall (n : nat),
S n = O ->
2 + 2 = 5.
Proof.
intros n contra. inversion contra. Qed.
Theorem inversion_ex5 : forall (n m : nat),
false = true ->
[n] = [m].
Proof.
intros n m contra. inversion contra. Qed.
(** If you find the principle of explosion confusing, remember
that these proofs are not actually showing that the conclusion of
the statement holds. Rather, they are arguing that the situation
described by the premise can never arise, so the implication is
vacuous. We'll explore the principle of explosion of more detail
in the next chapter. *)
(** **** Exercise: 1 star (inversion_ex6) *)
Example inversion_ex6 : forall (X : Type)
(x y z : X) (l j : list X),
x :: y :: l = [] ->
y :: l = z :: j ->
x = z.
Proof.
intros X x y z l j H0 H1.
inversion H0.
Qed.
(** To summarize this discussion, suppose [H] is a hypothesis in the
context or a previously proven lemma of the form
c a1 a2 ... an = d b1 b2 ... bm
for some constructors [c] and [d] and arguments [a1 ... an] and
[b1 ... bm]. Then [inversion H] has the following effect:
- If [c] and [d] are the same constructor, then, by the
injectivity of this constructor, we know that [a1 = b1], [a2 =
b2], etc.; [inversion H] adds these facts to the context, and
tries to use them to rewrite the goal.
- If [c] and [d] are different constructors, then the hypothesis
[H] is contradictory, and the current goal doesn't have to be
considered. In this case, [inversion H] marks the current goal
as completed and pops it off the goal stack. *)
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Using Tactics on Hypotheses *)
(** By default, most tactics work on the goal formula and leave
the context unchanged. However, most tactics also have a variant
that performs a similar operation on a statement in the context.
For example, the tactic [simpl in H] performs simplification in
the hypothesis named [H] in the context. *)
Theorem S_inj : forall (n m : nat) (b : bool),
beq_nat (S n) (S m) = b ->
beq_nat n m = b.
Proof.
intros n m b H. simpl in H. apply H. Qed.
(** Similarly, [apply L in H] matches some conditional statement
[L] (of the form [L1 -> L2], say) against a hypothesis [H] in the
context. However, unlike ordinary [apply] (which rewrites a goal
matching [L2] into a subgoal [L1]), [apply L in H] matches [H]
against [L1] and, if successful, replaces it with [L2].
In other words, [apply L in H] gives us a form of "forward
reasoning": from [L1 -> L2] and a hypothesis matching [L1], it
produces a hypothesis matching [L2]. By contrast, [apply L] is
"backward reasoning": it says that if we know [L1->L2] and we are
trying to prove [L2], it suffices to prove [L1].
Here is a variant of a proof from above, using forward reasoning
throughout instead of backward reasoning. *)
Theorem silly3' : forall (n : nat),
(beq_nat n 5 = true -> beq_nat (S (S n)) 7 = true) ->
true = beq_nat n 5 ->
true = beq_nat (S (S n)) 7.
Proof.
intros n eq H.
symmetry in H. apply eq in H. symmetry in H.
apply H. Qed.
(** Forward reasoning starts from what is _given_ (premises,
previously proven theorems) and iteratively draws conclusions from
them until the goal is reached. Backward reasoning starts from
the _goal_, and iteratively reasons about what would imply the
goal, until premises or previously proven theorems are reached.
If you've seen informal proofs before (for example, in a math or
computer science class), they probably used forward reasoning. In
general, idiomatic use of Coq tends to favor backward reasoning,
but in some situations the forward style can be easier to think
about. *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, recommended (plus_n_n_injective) *)
(** Practice using "in" variants in this exercise. (Hint: use
[plus_n_Sm].) *)
Lemma double_injective : forall n m,
double n = double m -> n = m.
Proof.
intros n. induction n as [|n'].
- simpl. intros m eq. destruct m as [|m'].
+ reflexivity.
+ inversion eq.
- simpl. intros m eq. destruct m as [|m'].
+ inversion eq.
+ apply f_equal. apply IHn'. inversion eq. reflexivity.
Qed.
Theorem plus_n_n_injective : forall n m,
n + n = m + m ->
n = m.
Proof.
intros n m H.
rewrite <- double_plus in H. rewrite <- double_plus in H.
apply double_injective in H.
apply H.
Qed.
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Varying the Induction Hypothesis *)
(** Sometimes it is important to control the exact form of the
induction hypothesis when carrying out inductive proofs in Coq.
In particular, we need to be careful about which of the
assumptions we move (using [intros]) from the goal to the context
before invoking the [induction] tactic. For example, suppose
we want to show that the [double] function is injective -- i.e.,
that it always maps different arguments to different results:
Theorem double_injective: forall n m,
double n = double m -> n = m.
The way we _start_ this proof is a bit delicate: if we begin with
intros n. induction n.
all is well. But if we begin it with
intros n m. induction n.
we get stuck in the middle of the inductive case... *)
Theorem double_injective_FAILED : forall n m,
double n = double m ->
n = m.
Proof.
intros n m. induction n as [| n'].
- (* n = O *) simpl. intros eq. destruct m as [| m'].
+ (* m = O *) reflexivity.
+ (* m = S m' *) inversion eq.
- (* n = S n' *) intros eq. destruct m as [| m'].
+ (* m = O *) inversion eq.
+ (* m = S m' *) apply f_equal.
(** At this point, the induction hypothesis, [IHn'], does not give us
[n' = m'] -- there is an extra [S] in the way -- so the goal is
not provable. *)
Abort.
(** What went wrong? *)
(** The problem is that, at the point we invoke the induction
hypothesis, we have already introduced [m] into the context --
intuitively, we have told Coq, "Let's consider some particular [n]
and [m]..." and we now have to prove that, if [double n = double
m] for _these particular_ [n] and [m], then [n = m].
The next tactic, [induction n] says to Coq: We are going to show
the goal by induction on [n]. That is, we are going to prove, for
_all_ [n], that the proposition
- [P n] = "if [double n = double m], then [n = m]"
holds, by showing
- [P O]
(i.e., "if [double O = double m] then [O = m]") and
- [P n -> P (S n)]
(i.e., "if [double n = double m] then [n = m]" implies "if
[double (S n) = double m] then [S n = m]").
If we look closely at the second statement, it is saying something
rather strange: it says that, for a _particular_ [m], if we know
- "if [double n = double m] then [n = m]"
then we can prove
- "if [double (S n) = double m] then [S n = m]".
To see why this is strange, let's think of a particular [m] --
say, [5]. The statement is then saying that, if we know
- [Q] = "if [double n = 10] then [n = 5]"
then we can prove
- [R] = "if [double (S n) = 10] then [S n = 5]".
But knowing [Q] doesn't give us any help at all with proving
[R]! (If we tried to prove [R] from [Q], we would start with
something like "Suppose [double (S n) = 10]..." but then we'd be
stuck: knowing that [double (S n)] is [10] tells us nothing about
whether [double n] is [10], so [Q] is useless.) *)
(** To summarize: Trying to carry out this proof by induction on [n]
when [m] is already in the context doesn't work because we are
then trying to prove a relation involving _every_ [n] but just a
_single_ [m]. *)
(** The good proof of [double_injective] leaves [m] in the goal
statement at the point where the [induction] tactic is invoked on
[n]: *)
Theorem double_injective' : forall n m,
double n = double m ->
n = m.
Proof.
intros n. induction n as [| n'].
- (* n = O *) simpl. intros m eq. destruct m as [| m'].
+ (* m = O *) reflexivity.
+ (* m = S m' *) inversion eq.
- (* n = S n' *) simpl.
(** Notice that both the goal and the induction hypothesis are
different this time: the goal asks us to prove something more
general (i.e., to prove the statement for _every_ [m]), but the IH
is correspondingly more flexible, allowing us to choose any [m] we
like when we apply the IH. *)
intros m eq.
(** Now we've chosen a particular [m] and introduced the assumption
that [double n = double m]. Since we are doing a case analysis on
[n], we also need a case analysis on [m] to keep the two "in sync." *)
destruct m as [| m'].
+ (* m = O *) simpl.
(** The 0 case is trivial: *)
inversion eq.
+ (* m = S m' *)
apply f_equal.
(** At this point, since we are in the second branch of the [destruct
m], the [m'] mentioned in the context is the predecessor of the
[m] we started out talking about. Since we are also in the [S]
branch of the induction, this is perfect: if we instantiate the
generic [m] in the IH with the current [m'] (this instantiation is
performed automatically by the [apply] in the next step), then
[IHn'] gives us exactly what we need to finish the proof. *)
apply IHn'. inversion eq. reflexivity. Qed.
(** What you should take away from all this is that we need to be
careful about using induction to try to prove something too
specific: If we're proving a property of [n] and [m] by induction
on [n], we may need to leave [m] generic. *)
(** The following exercise requires the same pattern. *)
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars (beq_nat_true) *)
Theorem beq_nat_true : forall n m,
beq_nat n m = true -> n = m.
Proof.
intros n. induction n.
- intros m. simpl. destruct m.
+ reflexivity.
+ intros H. inversion H.
- intros m. simpl. induction m.
+ intros H. inversion H.
+ intros H. apply IHn in H. rewrite H. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 2 stars, advanced (beq_nat_true_informal) *)
(** Give a careful informal proof of [beq_nat_true], being as explicit
as possible about quantifiers. *)
(* FILL IN HERE *)
(** [] *)
(** The strategy of doing fewer [intros] before an [induction] to
obtain a more general IH doesn't always work by itself; sometimes
a little _rearrangement_ of quantified variables is needed.
Suppose, for example, that we wanted to prove [double_injective]
by induction on [m] instead of [n]. *)
Theorem double_injective_take2_FAILED : forall n m,
double n = double m ->
n = m.
Proof.
intros n m. induction m as [| m'].
- (* m = O *) simpl. intros eq. destruct n as [| n'].
+ (* n = O *) reflexivity.
+ (* n = S n' *) inversion eq.
- (* m = S m' *) intros eq. destruct n as [| n'].
+ (* n = O *) inversion eq.
+ (* n = S n' *) apply f_equal.
(* Stuck again here, just like before. *)
Abort.
(** The problem here is that, to do induction on [m], we must first
introduce [n]. (If we simply say [induction m] without
introducing anything first, Coq will automatically introduce [n]
for us!) *)
(** What can we do about this? One possibility is to rewrite the
statement of the lemma so that [m] is quantified before [n]. This
will work, but it's not nice: We don't want to have to twist the
statements of lemmas to fit the needs of a particular strategy for
proving them -- we want to state them in the most clear and
natural way. *)
(** What we can do instead is to first introduce all the quantified
variables and then _re-generalize_ one or more of them,
selectively taking variables out of the context and putting them
back at the beginning of the goal. The [generalize dependent]
tactic does this. *)
Theorem double_injective_take2 : forall n m,
double n = double m ->
n = m.
Proof.
intros n m.
(* [n] and [m] are both in the context *)
generalize dependent n.
(* Now [n] is back in the goal and we can do induction on
[m] and get a sufficiently general IH. *)
induction m as [| m'].
- (* m = O *) simpl. intros n eq. destruct n as [| n'].
+ (* n = O *) reflexivity.
+ (* n = S n' *) inversion eq.
- (* m = S m' *) intros n eq. destruct n as [| n'].
+ (* n = O *) inversion eq.
+ (* n = S n' *) apply f_equal.
apply IHm'. inversion eq. reflexivity. Qed.
(** Let's look at an informal proof of this theorem. Note that
the proposition we prove by induction leaves [n] quantified,
corresponding to the use of generalize dependent in our formal
proof.
_Theorem_: For any nats [n] and [m], if [double n = double m], then
[n = m].
_Proof_: Let [m] be a [nat]. We prove by induction on [m] that, for
any [n], if [double n = double m] then [n = m].
- First, suppose [m = 0], and suppose [n] is a number such
that [double n = double m]. We must show that [n = 0].
Since [m = 0], by the definition of [double] we have [double n =
0]. There are two cases to consider for [n]. If [n = 0] we are
done, since [m = 0 = n], as required. Otherwise, if [n = S n']
for some [n'], we derive a contradiction: by the definition of
[double], we can calculate [double n = S (S (double n'))], but
this contradicts the assumption that [double n = 0].
- Second, suppose [m = S m'] and that [n] is again a number such
that [double n = double m]. We must show that [n = S m'], with
the induction hypothesis that for every number [s], if [double s =
double m'] then [s = m'].
By the fact that [m = S m'] and the definition of [double], we
have [double n = S (S (double m'))]. There are two cases to
consider for [n].
If [n = 0], then by definition [double n = 0], a contradiction.
Thus, we may assume that [n = S n'] for some [n'], and again by
the definition of [double] we have [S (S (double n')) =
S (S (double m'))], which implies by inversion that [double n' =
double m']. Instantiating the induction hypothesis with [n'] thus
allows us to conclude that [n' = m'], and it follows immediately
that [S n' = S m']. Since [S n' = n] and [S m' = m], this is just
what we wanted to show. [] *)
(** Before we close this section and move on to some exercises, let's
digress briefly and use [beq_nat_true] to prove a similar property
about identifiers that we'll need in later chapters: *)
Theorem beq_id_true : forall x y,
beq_id x y = true -> x = y.
Proof.
intros [m] [n]. simpl. intros H.
assert (H' : m = n). { apply beq_nat_true. apply H.
}
rewrite H'. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, recommended (gen_dep_practice) *)
(** Prove this by induction on [l]. *)
Theorem nth_error_after_last: forall (n : nat) (X : Type) (l : list X),
length l = n ->
nth_error l n = None.
Proof.
intros n X l. generalize dependent n. induction l as [| h' l'].
- reflexivity.
- simpl. intros n H. induction n as [| n'].
+ inversion H.
+ simpl. apply S_injective in H. apply IHl' in H. apply H.
Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, optional (app_length_cons) *)
(** Prove this by induction on [l1], without using [app_length]
from [Lists]. *)
Theorem app_length_cons : forall (X : Type) (l1 l2 : list X)
(x : X) (n : nat),
length (l1 ++ (x :: l2)) = n ->
S (length (l1 ++ l2)) = n.
Proof.
intros X l1 l2 x n.
generalize dependent l2. generalize dependent x. generalize dependent n.
induction l1 as [|h1 l1'].
- simpl. intros n x l2 H. apply H.
- simpl. intros n x l2 H. induction n as [| n'].
+ inversion H.
+ apply S_injective in H. apply IHl1' in H. apply f_equal. apply H.
Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 4 stars, optional (app_length_twice) *)
(** Prove this by induction on [l], without using [app_length] from [Lists]. *)
Lemma length_simpl : forall (X:Type) (l1 l2 :list X) (x : X),
length (l1 ++ x :: l2) = S (length (l1 ++ l2)).
Proof.
intros. induction l1 as [ | x' l1'].
- reflexivity.
- simpl. rewrite IHl1'. reflexivity.
Qed.
Theorem app_length_twice : forall (X:Type) (n:nat) (l:list X),
length l = n ->
length (l ++ l) = n + n.
Proof.
intros X n l. generalize dependent n. induction l as [| x' l'].
- simpl. intros n H. rewrite <- H. reflexivity.
- simpl. intros n H. rewrite -> length_simpl. induction n as [| n'].
+ inversion H.
+ inversion H. rewrite H1. apply IHl' in H1.
simpl. rewrite H1. rewrite plus_n_Sm. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, optional (double_induction) *)
(** Prove the following principle of induction over two naturals. *)
Theorem double_induction: forall (P : nat -> nat -> Prop),
P 0 0 ->
(forall m, P m 0 -> P (S m) 0) ->
(forall n, P 0 n -> P 0 (S n)) ->
(forall m n, P m n -> P (S m) (S n)) ->
forall m n, P m n.
Proof.
intros P H H0 H1 H2 m n. generalize dependent m. induction n as [| n'].
- intros m. induction m as [| m'].
+ apply H.
+ apply H0. apply IHm'.
- intros m. induction m as [| m'].
+ apply H1. apply IHn'.
+ apply H2. apply IHn'.
Qed.
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Unfolding Definitions *)
(** It sometimes happens that we need to manually unfold a Definition
so that we can manipulate its right-hand side. For example, if we
define... *)
Definition square n := n * n.
(** ... and try to prove a simple fact about [square]... *)
Lemma square_mult : forall n m, square (n * m) = square n * square m.
Proof.
intros n m.
simpl.
(** ... we get stuck: [simpl] doesn't simplify anything at this point,
and since we haven't proved any other facts about [square], there
is nothing we can [apply] or [rewrite] with.
To make progress, we can manually [unfold] the definition of
[square]: *)
unfold square.
(** Now we have plenty to work with: both sides of the equality are
expressions involving multiplication, and we have lots of facts
about multiplication at our disposal. In particular, we know that
it is commutative and associative, and from these facts it is not
hard to finish the proof. *)
rewrite mult_assoc.
assert (H : n * m * n = n * n * m).
{ rewrite mult_comm. apply mult_assoc. }
rewrite H. rewrite mult_assoc. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** At this point, a deeper discussion of unfolding and simplification
is in order.
You may already have observed that tactics like [simpl],
[reflexivity], and [apply] will often unfold the definitions of
functions automatically when it allows them to make progress. For
example, if we define [foo m] to be the constant [5], *)
Definition foo (x: nat) := 5.
(** then the [simpl] in the following proof (or the [reflexivity], if
we omit the [simpl]) will unfold [foo m] to [(fun x => 5) m] and
then further simplify this expression to just [5]. *)
Fact silly_fact_1 : forall m, foo m + 1 = foo (m + 1) + 1.
Proof.
intros m.
simpl.
reflexivity.
Qed.
(** However, this automatic unfolding is rather conservative. For
example, if we define a slightly more complicated function
involving a pattern match... *)
Definition bar x :=
match x with
| O => 5
| S _ => 5
end.
(** ...then the analogous proof will get stuck: *)
Fact silly_fact_2_FAILED : forall m, bar m + 1 = bar (m + 1) + 1.
Proof.
intros m.
simpl. (* Does nothing! *)
Abort.
(** The reason that [simpl] doesn't make progress here is that it
notices that, after tentatively unfolding [bar m], it is left with
a match whose scrutinee, [m], is a variable, so the [match] cannot
be simplified further. (It is not smart enough to notice that the
two branches of the [match] are identical.) So it gives up on
unfolding [bar m] and leaves it alone. Similarly, tentatively
unfolding [bar (m+1)] leaves a [match] whose scrutinee is a
function application (that, itself, cannot be simplified, even
after unfolding the definition of [+]), so [simpl] leaves it
alone.
At this point, there are two ways to make progress. One is to use
[destruct m] to break the proof into two cases, each focusing on a
more concrete choice of [m] ([O] vs [S _]). In each case, the
[match] inside of [bar] can now make progress, and the proof is
easy to complete. *)
Fact silly_fact_2 : forall m, bar m + 1 = bar (m + 1) + 1.
Proof.
intros m.
destruct m.
- simpl. reflexivity.
- simpl. reflexivity.
Qed.
(** This approach works, but it depends on our recognizing that the
[match] hidden inside [bar] is what was preventing us from making
progress.
A more straightforward way to finish the proof is to explicitly
tell Coq to unfold [bar]. *)
Fact silly_fact_2' : forall m, bar m + 1 = bar (m + 1) + 1.
Proof.
intros m.
unfold bar.
(** Now it is apparent that we are stuck on the [match] expressions on
both sides of the [=], and we can use [destruct] to finish the
proof without thinking too hard. *)
destruct m.
- reflexivity.
- reflexivity.
Qed.
(* ################################################################# *)
(** * Using [destruct] on Compound Expressions *)
(** We have seen many examples where [destruct] is used to
perform case analysis of the value of some variable. But
sometimes we need to reason by cases on the result of some
_expression_. We can also do this with [destruct].
Here are some examples: *)
Definition sillyfun (n : nat) : bool :=
if beq_nat n 3 then false
else if beq_nat n 5 then false
else false.
Theorem sillyfun_false : forall (n : nat),
sillyfun n = false.
Proof.
intros n. unfold sillyfun.
destruct (beq_nat n 3).
- (* beq_nat n 3 = true *) reflexivity.
- (* beq_nat n 3 = false *) destruct (beq_nat n 5).
+ (* beq_nat n 5 = true *) reflexivity.
+ (* beq_nat n 5 = false *) reflexivity. Qed.
(** After unfolding [sillyfun] in the above proof, we find that
we are stuck on [if (beq_nat n 3) then ... else ...]. But either
[n] is equal to [3] or it isn't, so we can use [destruct (beq_nat
n 3)] to let us reason about the two cases.
In general, the [destruct] tactic can be used to perform case
analysis of the results of arbitrary computations. If [e] is an
expression whose type is some inductively defined type [T], then,
for each constructor [c] of [T], [destruct e] generates a subgoal
in which all occurrences of [e] (in the goal and in the context)
are replaced by [c]. *)
(** **** Exercise: 3 stars, optional (combine_split) *)
Theorem combine_split : forall X Y (l : list (X * Y)) l1 l2,
split l = (l1, l2) ->
combine l1 l2 = l.
Proof.
intros X Y l l1 l2 H. generalize dependent l. generalize l1.
induction l2 as [| h2 l2'].
- intros l0 l. generalize dependent l0. induction l as [|h l'].
+ intros l0 H. assert (l0 = []). { inversion H. reflexivity. } rewrite H0. reflexivity.
+ intros l0 H. inversion H. unfold app_list_pair in H1. Abort.
(** However, [destruct]ing compound expressions requires a bit of
care, as such [destruct]s can sometimes erase information we need
to complete a proof. *)
(** For example, suppose we define a function [sillyfun1] like
this: *)
Definition sillyfun1 (n : nat) : bool :=
if beq_nat n 3 then true
else if beq_nat n 5 then true
else false.
(** Now suppose that we want to convince Coq of the (rather
obvious) fact that [sillyfun1 n] yields [true] only when [n] is
odd. By analogy with the proofs we did with [sillyfun] above, it
is natural to start the proof like this: *)
Theorem sillyfun1_odd_FAILED : forall (n : nat),
sillyfun1 n = true ->
oddb n = true.
Proof.
intros n eq. unfold sillyfun1 in eq.
destruct (beq_nat n 3).
(* stuck... *)
Abort.
(** We get stuck at this point because the context does not
contain enough information to prove the goal! The problem is that
the substitution performed by [destruct] is too brutal -- it threw
away every occurrence of [beq_nat n 3], but we need to keep some
memory of this expression and how it was destructed, because we
need to be able to reason that, since [beq_nat n 3 = true] in this
branch of the case analysis, it must be that [n = 3], from which
it follows that [n] is odd.
What we would really like is to substitute away all existing
occurences of [beq_nat n 3], but at the same time add an equation
to the context that records which case we are in. The [eqn:]
qualifier allows us to introduce such an equation, giving it a